Menu Expand
  • Hochschule für angewandtes Management GmbH
  • EN / DE
  • Login

Economic Analysis of Institutions: Nominalism and Definition by Effect

Cite JOURNAL ARTICLE

Style

Stettler, M. Economic Analysis of Institutions: Nominalism and Definition by Effect. Journal of Contextual Economics – Schmollers Jahrbuch, 99999(), 1-20. https://doi.org/10.3790/schm.2025.401891
Stettler, Michael A. "Economic Analysis of Institutions: Nominalism and Definition by Effect" Journal of Contextual Economics – Schmollers Jahrbuch 99999., 2025, 1-20. https://doi.org/10.3790/schm.2025.401891
Stettler, Michael A. (2025): Economic Analysis of Institutions: Nominalism and Definition by Effect, in: Journal of Contextual Economics – Schmollers Jahrbuch, vol. 99999, iss. , 1-20, [online] https://doi.org/10.3790/schm.2025.401891

Format

Economic Analysis of Institutions: Nominalism and Definition by Effect

Stettler, Michael A.

Journal of Contextual Economics – Schmollers Jahrbuch, Online First : pp. 1–20

Additional Information

Article Details

Author Details

Michael A. Stettler, School of Economics, University of Johannesburg, Johannesburg, South Africa

References

  1. Alchian, A. A. and H. Demsetz. 1972. “Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization.” American Economic Review 62 (5): 777 – 95.  Google Scholar
  2. Allen, D. W. 2012. The Institutional Revolution: Measurement and the Emergence of the Modern Economic World. Chicago: Chicago University Press.  Google Scholar
  3. Barzel, Y. 1989. Economic Analysis of Property Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University. Press.  Google Scholar
  4. Berquist, D. 2013. “Duane Berquist on Ethics.” Accessed 5 Feb 2025. https://archive.org/details/duaneberquistonethics.  Google Scholar
  5. Busino, G. 2000. “The signification of Vilfredo Pareto’s sociology.” Revue Européenne des Sciences Sociales. XXXVIII-117: 217 – 228.  Google Scholar
  6. Card, D. and A. B. Krueger. 1994. “Minimum Wages and Employment: A Case Study of the Fast-Food Industry in New Jersey and Pennsylvania.” American Economic Review 84 (4): 772 – 793.  Google Scholar
  7. Coase, R. 1937. “The Nature of the Firm.” Economica 4 (16): 386 – 405.  Google Scholar
  8. Coase, R. 1960. “The Problem of Social Cost.” Journal of Law & Economics 30 (1): 1 – 44.  Google Scholar
  9. Cooter, R. 1984. “Prices and Sanctions.” Columbia Law Review 84 (6): 1523 – 1560.  Google Scholar
  10. Darwin, C. 1859. On the Origins of Species. London: John Murray.  Google Scholar
  11. Demsetz, H. 1967. “Toward a Theory of Property Rights.” American Economic Review 57 (2): 347 – 359.  Google Scholar
  12. Demuynck, T. and P. Hjertstrand. 2019. “Samuelson’s Approach to Revealed Preference Theory: Some Recent Advances.” In: Paul Samuelson: Master of Modern Economics, edited by R. G. Anderson, W. A. Barnett, and R. A. Cord. London: Palgrave Macmillan.  Google Scholar
  13. De Waal, C. 2010. “The History of Philosophy Conceived as a Struggle Between Nominalism and Realism.” Semiotica 179: 295 – 313.  Google Scholar
  14. Easterbrook, F. H. and D. R. Fischel. 1982. “Antitrust Suits by Targets of Tender Offers.” Michigan Law Review 80: 1155 – 1178.  Google Scholar
  15. Easterbrook, F. H. and D. R. Fischel. 1989. “The Corporate Contract.” Columbia Law Review 89 (7): 1416 – 1448.  Google Scholar
  16. Elster, J. 1989. “Social Norms and Economic Theory.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 3 (4): 99 – 117.  Google Scholar
  17. Fisher, I. 1918. “Is ‘Utility’ the Most Suitable Term for the Concept it is Used to Denote?” American Economic Review 8 (2): 335 – 337.  Google Scholar
  18. Forster, P. 2011. Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.  Google Scholar
  19. Friedman, Milton. 1953. “The Methodology of Positive Economics.” In: Essays in Positive Economics, edited by Milton Friedman. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.  Google Scholar
  20. Greif, A. and J. Mokyr. 2016. “Institutions and Economic History: A Critique of Professor McCloskey.” Journal of Institutional Economics 12 (1): 29 – 41.  Google Scholar
  21. Guala, F. 2019. “Preferences: Neither Behavioural nor Mental.” Economics and Philosophy 35 (3): 383 – 401.  Google Scholar
  22. Gul, F. and W. Pesendorfer. 2010. “The Case for Mindless Economics.” In: The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics: A Handbook, edited by A. Caplin and A. Schotter. Oxford: Oxford Academic.  Google Scholar
  23. Hildenbrand, W. 1999. “On the Empirical Content of Economic Theories.” In: Economics Beyond the Millennium, edited by A. P. Kirman and L. Gérard-Varet. Oxford: Oxford Academic.  Google Scholar
  24. Hobbes, T. (1651) 1998. Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.  Google Scholar
  25. Hochschild, J. 2014. “What’s Wrong with Ockham: Reassessing the Role of Nominalism in the Dissolution of the West.” Anamnesis: 1 – 13.  Google Scholar
  26. Houthakker, H. S. 1950. “Revealed Preference and the Utility Function.” Economica 17 (66): 159 – 174.  Google Scholar
  27. Jensen, M. C. and W. H. Meckling. 1976. “Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure.” Journal of Financial Economics 3 (4): 305 – 360.  Google Scholar
  28. Kirman, A. 2021. “Walras or Pareto: Who is to Blame for the State of Modern Economic Theory?” Review of Political Economy 33 (2): 280 – 302.  Google Scholar
  29. Lachmann, L. M. 1963. “Wirtschaftsordnung und wirtschaftliche Institutionen.” ORDO: Jahrbuch Für Die Ordnung von Wirtschaft Und Gesellschaft 14: 63 – 77.  Google Scholar
  30. Leff, A. A. 1974. “Economic Analysis of Law: Some Realism about Nominalism.” Virginia Law Review 60 (3): 451 – 482.  Google Scholar
  31. Machuga, R. 2011. Life, the Universe, and Everything: An Aristotelian Philosophy for a Scientific Age. Cambridge: Cascade Books.  Google Scholar
  32. Mayr, E. 1988. Toward a New Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.  Google Scholar
  33. McCloskey, D. N. 1983. “The Rhetoric of Economics.” Journal of Economic Literature 21 (2): 481 – 517.  Google Scholar
  34. McCloskey, D. N. 1985. The Rhetoric of Economics. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.  Google Scholar
  35. McCloskey, D. N. 2016. “Max U versus Humanomics: A Critique of Neo-Institutionalism.” Journal of Institutional Economics 12 (1): 1 – 27.  Google Scholar
  36. McCloskey, D. N. 2022. Beyond Positivism, Behaviorism, and Neoinstitutionalism in Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.  Google Scholar
  37. McCloskey, D. N. and P. Silvestri. 2021. “Beyond Behaviorism, Positivism, and Neo-Institutionalism in Economics: A Conversation with Deirdre Nansen McCloskey.” Journal of Institutional Economics 17 (5): 717 – 728.  Google Scholar
  38. Merrill, T. W. and H. E. Smith. 2001. “What Happened to Property in Law and Economics?” The Yale Law Journal 111 (2): 357 – 398.  Google Scholar
  39. Mittermaier, K. 2020. The Hand Behind the Invisible Hand: Dogmatic and Pragmatic Attitudes on Free Markets. Bristol: Bristol University Press.  Google Scholar
  40. Mittermaier, K. 2023. A Realist Philosophy of Economics. Bristol: Bristol University Press.  Google Scholar
  41. Mittermaier, K. 2025 (forthcoming). Subjectivism in Economics and Philosophy. Bristol: Bristol University Press.  Google Scholar
  42. North, D. C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.  Google Scholar
  43. Pareto, V. (1906) 1971. Manual of Political Economy. Translated by A. Schwier. London: Macmillan.  Google Scholar
  44. Pareto, V. 1935. The Mind and Society. Vol. 1. “Non-Logical Conduct.” Edited by A. Livingston. New York: Harcourt.  Google Scholar
  45. Posner, R. (1973) 1986. The Economic Analysis of Law. Third edition. Boston: Littler Brown.  Google Scholar
  46. Rubin, P. H. 1977. Why Is the Common Law Efficient?” Journal of Legal Studies 6 (1): 51 – 63.  Google Scholar
  47. Samuelson, P. A. 1938. “A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer’s Behaviour.” Economica 5 (17): 61 – 71.  Google Scholar
  48. Smith, A. (1759) 2000. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. The Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith, Vol. 1. Reprint. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.  Google Scholar
  49. Smith, A. (1776) 1952. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Brittanica.  Google Scholar
  50. Smith, H. E. 2012. “Property as the Law of Things.” Harvard Law Review 125 (7): 1691 – 1726.  Google Scholar
  51. Stigler, G. J. and G. S. Becker. 1977. “De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum.” American Economic Review 67 (2): 76 – 90.  Google Scholar
  52. Thurman, W. 2023. “Where Lies the Bundle of Sticks? A comment on Bart Wilson’s ‘The Primacy of Property’.” Journal of Institutional Economics 19 (2): 285 – 287.  Google Scholar
  53. Varian, H. R. 2006. “Revealed Preference.” In: Samuelsonian Economics and the Twenty-First Century, edited by M. Szenberg, L. Ramrattanand, and A. A. Gottesman, 99 – 115. Oxford: Oxford University Press.  Google Scholar
  54. Wilson, B. J. 2020. The Property Species: Mine, Yours, and the Human Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.  Google Scholar
  55. Wilson, B. J. 2023. “The Primacy of Property; or the Subordination of Property Rights.” Journal of Institutional Economics 19 (1): 251 – 267.  Google Scholar

Abstract

Neo-institutional economics covers various subject areas that are not the traditional domain of economics, while still employing the tools of economic analysis such as: rational choice theory and equilibrium theory. Many fields of study, including law, firms, property, etc., are characterised as efficient institutions. It is a flawed approach, because neo-institutionalism portrays past events, what Karl Mittermaier called ex-post facts, as if they were structural facts, or ex-ante facts. In Samuelson’s revealed preference theory, choices (ex-post facts), are assigned a new name, viz. revealed preferences (ex-ante facts), and preferences are reduced to their effects. Neo-institutionalism follows Samuelson in this regard, defining things by their effect: defining institutions as constraints, property as property rights, firms as contracts, etc. In doing so, neo-institutionalism eliminates the distinctions between concepts; the effect can stand as the primary aspect of the institution, and institution becomes a name for a constraint. This mixes up two orders of fact, giving past events (ex-post facts) a name associated with greater permanence (ex-ante facts). These theoretical moves belong to a nominalist Weltanschauung, one already proposed by Pareto, who called himself the most nominalist of nominalists.